Search

The Online Encyclopedia and Dictionary

 
     
 

Encyclopedia

Dictionary

Quotes

 

Equality (mathematics)

(Redirected from Equals sign)
See also the disambiguation page title equality.

In mathematics, two mathematical objects are considered equal if they are precisely the same in every way. This defines a binary predicate, equality, denoted "="; x = y iff x and y are equal. Equivalence in the general sense is provided by the construction of a equivalence relation between two elements. A statement that two expressions denote equal quantities is an equation.

Beware that sometimes a statement of the form "A = B" may not be an equality. For example, the statement T(n) = O(n2) means that T(n) grows at the order of n2. It is not an equality, because the sign "=" in the statement is not the equality sign; indeed, it is meaningless to write O(n2) = T(n). See Big O notation for more on this.

Given a set A, the restriction of equality to the set A is a binary relation, which is at once reflexive, symmetric, antisymmetric, and transitive. Indeed it is the only relation on A with all these properties. Dropping the requirement of antisymmetry yields the notion of equivalence relation. Conversely, given any equivalence relation R, we can form the quotient set A/R, and the equivalence relation will 'descend' to equality in A/R. Note that it may be impractical to compute with equivalence classes: one solution often used is to look for a distinguished normal form representative of a class.

Contents

Logical formations

Predicate logic contains standard axioms for equality that formalise Leibniz's law, put forward by the philosopher Gottfried Leibniz in the 1600s. Leibniz's idea was that two things are identical if and only if they have precisely the same properties. To formalise this, we wish to say

Given any x and y, x = y if and only if, given any predicate P, P(x) iff P(y).

However, in first order logic, we cannot quantify over predicates. Thus, we need to use an axiom schema:

Given any x and y, if x equals y, then P(x) iff P(y).

This axiom schema, valid for any predicate P in one variable, takes care of only one direction of Leibniz's law; if x and y are equal, then they have the same properties. We can take care of the other direction by simply postulating:

Given any x, x equals x.

Then if x and y have the same properties, then in particular they are the same with respect to the predicate P given by P(z) iff x = z. Since P(x) holds, P(y) must also hold, so x = y.

Some basic logical properties of equality

The substitution property states:

  • For any quantities a and b and any expression F(x), if a = b, then F(a) = F(b) (if either side makes sense).

In first order logic, this is a schema, since we can't quantify over expressions like F (which would be a functional predicate).

Some specific examples of this are:

  • For any real numbers a, b, and c, if a = b, then a + c = b + c (here F(x) is x + c);
  • For any real numbers a, b, and c, if a = b, then a - c = b - c (here F(x) is x - c);
  • For any real numbers a, b, and c, if a = b, then ac = bc (here F(x) is xc);
  • For any real numbers a, b, and c, if a = b and c is not zero, then a/c = b/c (here F(x) is x/c).

The reflexive property states:

For any quantity a, a = a.

This property is generally used in mathematical proofs as an intermediate step.

The symmetric property states:

  • For any quantities a and b, if a = b, then b = a.

The transitive property states:

  • For any quantities a, b, and c, if a = b and b = c, then a = c.

The binary relation "is approximately equal" between real numbers or other things, even if more precisely defined, is not transitive (it may seem so at first sight, but many small differences can add up to something big). However, equality almost everywhere is transitive.

Although the symmetric and transitive properties are often seen as fundamental, they can be proved from the substitution and reflexive properties.

History of the notation

The equal sign, equals sign, or =, used to indicate the result of some arithmetical operation, was invented in 1557 by Robert Recorde.

Growing tired of writing out the words "is equalle to:" [sic], Recorde employed the symbol in his work The Whetstone of Witte. The rationale for choosing that sign is that its two lines are equal in length, indicating that the quantities so joined are also equal. The invention is commemorated in St Mary's Church, Tenby, Wales.

The symbol used to denote when something is approximately equal to something else is ≈, and the symbol used to denote when something is not equal to something else is ≠. The symbol ≡ is often used to indicate an identity rather than an equation.

The equal sign that is currently used in Japan (・) also is used as a punctuation to separate the first and last names when a western person's name is written in Katakana.

See also

External links

Last updated: 08-08-2005 05:10:30
The contents of this article are licensed from Wikipedia.org under the GNU Free Documentation License. How to see transparent copy