Online Encyclopedia Search Tool

Your Online Encyclopedia

 

Online Encylopedia and Dictionary Research Site

Online Encyclopedia Free Search Online Encyclopedia Search    Online Encyclopedia Browse    welcome to our free dictionary for your research of every kind

Online Encyclopedia



Kripke semantics

(Redirected from Relational semantics)

Kripke semantics (also known as possible world semantics, relational semantics, or frame semantics) is a formal semantics for modal logic systems, created in late 1950's and early 1960's by Saul Kripke. It was later adapted to other non-classical logics, most importantly intuitionistic logic. The discovery of Kripke semantics was a major breakthrough in the development of non-classical logics, as the model theory of such logics was virtually nonexistent before Kripke.

Contents

Semantics of modal logic

For our purposes, the language of modal logic consists of propositional variables, the reader's favorite complete set of Boolean connectives (such as {→,¬} or {∨,∧,¬}), and the modal operator \Box (“necessity”). The dual modal operator \Diamond (“possibility”) is defined as an abbreviation: \Diamond A:=\neg\Box\neg A. See the page on modal logic for more background.

Basic definitions

A Kripke frame is a pair <W,R>, where W is a non-empty set, and R is a binary relation on W. Elements of W are called nodes or worlds, and R is known as the accessibility relation.

A Kripke model is a triple <W,R,⊩>, where <W,R> is a Kripke frame, and ⊩ is a relation between nodes of W and modal formulas, such that:

  • w\Vdash\neg A if and only if w\not\Vdash A,
  • w\Vdash A\to B if and only if w\not\Vdash A or w\Vdash B,
  • w\Vdash\Box A if and only if \forall u\,(w\; R\; u \Rightarrow u\Vdash A).

We read w ⊩A as “w satisfies A”, “A is satisfied in w”, or “w forces A”. The relation ⊩ is called the satisfaction relation, evaluation, or forcing relation. Notice that the satisfaction relation is uniquely determined by its value on propositional variables.

A formula A is valid in:

  • a model <W,R,⊩>, if w ⊩A for all w ∈W,
  • a frame <W,R>, if it is valid in <W,R,⊩> for all possible choices of ⊩,
  • a class C of frames or models, if it is valid in every member of C.

We define Thm(C) as the set of all formulas which are valid in C. Conversly, if X is a set of formulas, let Mod(X) be the class of all frames which validate every formula from X.

A modal logic (i.e., a set of formulas) L is sound with respect to a class of frames C, if LThm(C). L is complete wrt C if LThm(C).

Correspondence and completeness

Semantics is useful for investigation of a logic (i.e., a derivation system) only if the semantical entailment relation faithfully reflects its syntactical counterpart, the consequence relation (derivability). It is thus vital to know which modal logics are sound and complete wrt a class of Kripke frames, and if so, to determine which class it is.

For any class C of Kripke frames, Thm(C) is a normal modal logic; in particular, theorems of the minimal normal modal logic, K, are valid in every Kripke model. Unfortunately, the converse does not hold in general: there are normal modal logics which are Kripke incomplete. In practice, this is not a problem, as most of the modal systems which are actually studied are complete wrt classes of frames described by simple conditions.

A normal modal logic L corresponds to a class of frames C, if C=Mod(L). In other words, C is the largest class of frames such that L is sound wrt C; it follows that L is Kripke complete if and only if it is complete with respect to its corresponding class.

As an example, consider the schema T: \Box A\to A. T is valid in any reflexive frame <W,R>: if w ⊩\Box A, then w ⊩A since w R w. On the other hand, a frame which validates T has to be reflexive: fix w ∈W, and define satisfaction of a propositional variable p as follows: u ⊩p iff w R u. Then w ⊩\Box p, thus w ⊩p by T, which means w R w using the definition of ⊩. We see that T corresponds to the class of reflexive Kripke frames.

It is often much easier to characterize the corresponding class of L than to prove its completeness, thus correspondence serves as a guide to completeness proofs. Correspondence is also used to show incompleteness of modal logics: suppose that L1L2 are normal modal logics which correspond to the same class of frames, such that L1 does not prove all theorems of L2. Then L1 is Kripke incomplete. For example, the schema \Box(A\equiv\Box A)\to\Box A generates an incomplete logic, because it corresponds to the same class of frames as GL (viz. transitive and conversely well-founded frames), but it does not prove \Box A\to\Box\Box A.

A list of common modal axioms together with their corresponding classes is given in the table below. Beware: naming of the axioms often varies.


Common modal axiom schemata
name axiom frame condition
T \Box A\to A reflexive
4 \Box A\to\Box\Box A transitive
D \Box A\to\Diamond A serial: \forall w\,\exists v\,(w\;R\;v)
B A\to\Box\Diamond A symmetric
5 \Diamond A\to\Box\Diamond A Euclidean: w\;R\;u\land w\;R\;v\Rightarrow u\;R\;v
L \Box(\Box A\to A)\to\Box A R transitive, R-1 well-founded
Grz \Box(\Box(A\to\Box A)\to A)\to A R reflexive and transitive, R-1Id well-founded
3 \Box(\Box A\to B)\lor\Box(\Box B\to A) w\;R\;u\land w\;R\;v\Rightarrow u\;R\;v\lor v\;R\;u
1 \Box\Diamond A\to\Diamond\Box A (a complicated second-order property)
2 \Diamond\Box A\to\Box\Diamond A w\;R\;u\land w\;R\;v\Rightarrow\exists x\,(u\;R\;x\land v\;R\;x)


Here is a list of several common modal systems. Frame conditions for some of them were simplified: the logics are complete with respect to the frame classes given in the table, but they may correspond to a larger class of frames.


Common normal modal logics
name axioms frame condition
K K all frames
T KT reflexive
K4 K4 transitive
S4 KT4 preorder
S5 KT5=KDB4 R=W × W
S4.3 KT43 total preorder
S4.1 KT41 preorder, \forall w\,\exists u\,(w\;R\;u\land\forall v\,(u\;R\;v\Rightarrow u=v))
S4.2 KT42 directed preorder
GL KL=K4L finite strict partial order
Grz, S4Grz KGrz=KT4Grz finite partial order
D KD serial
D45 KD45 transitive, serial, and Euclidean


Canonical models

For any normal modal logic L, we can construct a Kripke model (called the canonical model), which validates the theorems of L, and only them. Canonical Kripke models play a similar rôle as the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra construction in algebraic semantics.

A set X of formulas is L-consistent, if there does not exist a proof of contradiction using formulas from X, theorems of L, and Modus Ponens. A maximal L-consistent set (L-MCS for short) is an L-consistent set which has no proper L-consistent superset.

The canonical model of L is a Kripke model <W,R,⊩>, where W is the set of all L-MCS, and the relations R and ⊩ are as follows:

X\;R\;Y iff for every formula A, if \Box A\in X then A\in Y,
X\Vdash A iff A\in X.

The canonical model is a model of L, as every L-MCS contains all theorems of L. By Zorn's lemma, each L-consistent set is contained in an L-MCS, in particular every formula unprovable in L has a counterexample in the canonical model.

The main application of canonical models are completeness proofs. For example, properties of the canonical model of K immediately imply completeness of K with respect to the class of all Kripke frames. This argument does not work for arbitrary L, because there is no guarantee that the underlying frame of the canonical model satisfies the frame conditions of L.

We say that a formula or a set X of formulas is canonical with respect to a property P of Kripke frames, if

  • X is valid in every frame which satisfies P,
  • for any normal modal logic L which contains X, the underlying frame of the canonical model of L satisfies P.

Clearly, a union of canonical sets of formulas is itself canonical. It follows from the preceding discussion that any logic axiomatized by a canonical set of formulas is Kripke complete, and compact.

The axioms T, 4, D, B, 5, 3, 2 (and thus any combination of them) are canonical. GL and Grz are not canonical, because they are not compact. The axiom 1 by itself is not canonical (Goldblatt, 1991), but the combined logic S4.1 (in fact, even K4.1) is canonical.

In general, it is undecidable whether a given axiom is canonical. Nevertheless, we know a nice sufficient condition: H. Sahlqvist has identified a broad class of formulas (now called Sahlqvist formulas) such that

  • a Sahlqvist formula is canonical,
  • the class of frames corresponding to a Sahlqvist formula is first-order definable,
  • there is an algorithm which computes the corresponding frame condition to a given Sahlqvist formula.

This is a very powerful criterion; for example, all axioms listed above as canonical are in fact (equivalent to) Sahlqvist formulas.

Finite model property

A logic has the finite model property (FMP) if it is complete wrt a class of finite frames. One of the main applications of this notion is the decidability question: it follows from Post's theorem that a recursively axiomatized modal logic L which has FMP is decidable, provided it is decidable whether a given finite frame is a model of L. In particular, every finitely axiomatizable logic with FMP is decidable.

There are various methods for establishing FMP for a given logic. Refinements and extensions of the canonical model construction often work, using tools such as filtration or unravelling. As another possibility, completeness proofs based on cut-free sequent calculi usually produce finite models directly.

Most of the modal systems used in practice (including all listed above) have FMP.

In some cases, we can use FMP to prove Kripke completeness of a logic: every normal modal logic is complete wrt a class of modal algebra s, and a finite modal algebra can be transformed into a Kripke frame. As an example, Robert Bull proved using this method that every normal extension of S4.3 has FMP, and is Kripke complete.

Polymodal logics

Kripke semantics has a straightforward generalization to logics with more than one modality. A Kripke frame for a language with \{\Box_i;\,i\in I\} as the set of its necessity operators consists of a non-empty set W equipped with binary relations Ri for each i ∈I. The definition of a satisfaction relation is modified as follows:

w\Vdash\Box_i A if and only if \forall u\,(w\;R_i\;u\Rightarrow u\Vdash A).

A simplified semantics, discovered by Tim Carlson, is often used for polymodal provability logics. A Carlson model is a structure <W,R,{Di}iI,⊩> with a single accessibility relation R, and subsets Di ⊆ W for each modality. Satisfaction is defined as

w\Vdash\Box_i A if and only if \forall u\in D_i\,(w\;R\;u\Rightarrow u\Vdash A).

Carlson models are easier to visualize and to work with than usual polymodal Kripke models; there are, however, Kripke complete polymodal logics which are Carlson incomplete.

Semantics of intuitionistic logic

Kripke semantics for the intuitionistic logic follows the same principles as the semantics of modal logic, but it uses a different definition of satisfaction.

An intuitionistic Kripke model is a triple <W,≤,⊩>, where <W,≤> is a transitive and reflexive Kripke frame (i.e., the accessibility relation is a preorder), and ⊩ satisfies the following conditions:

  • if p is a propositional variable, w ≤ u, and w ⊩p, then u ⊩p (persistency condition),
  • w ⊩A ∧ B if and only if w ⊩A and w ⊩B,
  • w ⊩A ∨ B if and only if w ⊩A or w ⊩B,
  • w ⊩A → B if and only if for all u ≥ w, u ⊩A implies u ⊩B,
  • not w ⊩⊥.

Intuitionistic logic is sound and complete with respect to its Kripke semantics, and it has FMP.


Intuitionistic first-order logic

Let L be a first-order language. A Kripke model of L is a triple <W,≤,{Mw}wW>, where <W,≤> is an intuitionistic Kripke frame, Mw is a (classical) L-structure for each node w ∈W, and the following compatibility conditions hold whenever u ≤ v:

  • the domain of Mu is included in the domain of Mv,
  • realizations of function symbols in Mu and Mv agree on elements of Mu,
  • for each n-ary predicate P and elements a1,...,an ∈Mu: if P(a1,...,an) holds in Mu, then it holds in Mv.

Given an evaluation e of variables by elements of Mw, we define the satisfaction relation w ⊩A[e]:

  • w ⊩P(t1,...,tn)[e] if and only if P(t1[e],...,tn[e]) holds in Mw,
  • w ⊩(A ∧ B)[e] if and only if w ⊩A[e] and w ⊩B[e],
  • w ⊩(A ∨ B)[e] if and only if w ⊩A[e] or w ⊩B[e],
  • w ⊩(A → B)[e] if and only if for all u ≥ w, u ⊩A[e] implies u ⊩B[e],
  • not w ⊩⊥[e],
  • w ⊩(∃x A)[e] if and only if there exists an a ∈Mw such that w ⊩A[e(xa)],
  • w ⊩(∀x A)[e] if and only if for every u ≥ w and every a ∈Mu, u ⊩A[e(xa)].

Here e(xa) is the evaluation which gives x the value a, and otherwise agrees with e.


Kripke-Joyal semantics

As part of the quite independent development of sheaf theory, it was realised around 1965 that Kripke semantics was intimately related to the treatment of existential quantification in topos theory. That is, the 'local' aspect of existence for sections of a sheaf was a kind of logic of the 'possible'. Since this development was the work of a number of people, and was more in the nature of a conceptual insight than a theorem, it is not so easy to attribute credit. The name Kripke-Joyal semantics is often used in this connection.

Model constructions

As in the classical model theory, there are methods for constructing a new Kripke model from other models.

The natural homomorphisms in Kripke semantics are called p-morphisms (which is short for pseudo-epimorphism, but the latter term is rarely used). A p-morphism of Kripke frames <W,R> and <W’,R’> is a mapping f:W → W’ such that

  • f preserves the accessibility relation, i.e., u R v implies f(u) R’ f(v),
  • whenever f(u) R’ v’, there is a v ∈ W such that f(v)=v’.

A p-morphism of Kripke models <W,R,⊩> and <W’,R’,⊩’> is a p-morphism of their underlying frames f:W → W’, which satisfies

w ⊩p iff f(w) ⊩’p, for any propositional variable p.

P-morphisms are a special kind of bisimulations. In general, a bisimulation between frames <W,R> and <W’,R’> is a relation B ⊆ W × W’, which satisfies the following “zig-zag” property:

  • if u B u’ and u R v, there exists v’ ∈ W’ such that v B v’,
  • if u B u’ and u’ R’ v’, there exists v ∈ W such that v B v’.

A bisimulation of models is additionally required to preserve forcing of atomic formulas:

if w B w’, then w ⊩p iff w’ ⊩’p, for any propositional variable p.

The key property which follows from this definition is that bisimulations (hence also p-morphisms) of models preserve the satisfaction of all formulas, not only propositional variables.

We can transform a Kripke model into a tree using unravelling. Given a model <W,R,⊩> and a fixed node w0 ∈ W, we define a model <W’,R’,⊩’>, where W’ is the set of all finite sequences s=<w0,w1,...,wn> such that wi R wi+1 for all i<n, and s ⊩p iff wn ⊩p for a propositional variable p. The definition of the accessibility relation R’ varies; in the simplest case we put

<w0,w1,...,wnR’ <w0,w1,...,wn,wn+1>,

but many applications need the reflexive and/or transitive closure of this relation, or similar modifications.

Filtration is a variant of a p-morphism. Let X be a set of formulas closed under taking subformulas. An X-filtration of a model <W,R,⊩> is a mapping f from W to a model <W’,R’,⊩’> such that

  • f is a surjection,
  • f preserves the accessibility relation, and (in both directions) satisfaction of variables p ∈ X,
  • if f(u) R’ f(v) and u ⊩\Box A, where \Box AX, then v ⊩A.

It follows that f preserves satisfaction of all formulas from X. In typical applications, we take f as the projection onto the quotient of W over the relation

u ≡X v iff for all A ∈X, u ⊩A iff v ⊩A.

As in the case of unravelling, the definition of the accessibility relation on the quotient varies.

History and Terminology

Kripke semantics does not originate with Kripke, but instead the idea of giving semantics in the style given above, that is based on valuations made that are relative to nodes, predates Kripke by a long margin:

  • Carnap seems to have been the first to have the idea that one can give a possible world semantics for the modalities of necessity and possibility be means of giving the valuation function a parameter that ranges over Leibnizian possible worlds. Bayart develops this idea further, but neither give recursive definitions of satisfaction in the style introduced by Tarski;
  • Jónsson and Tarski give a presentation of an approach to semantics that is still influential in modern research on modal logic, namely the algebraic approach, which contains many of the key ideas of Kripke semantics. They apply the ideas to the semantics of intuitionistic logic, but fail to see the relationship to modal logic;
  • Kanger gave a rather more complex approach to the interpretation of modal logic, but one that contains many of the key ideas of Kripke's approach. He first noted the relationship between conditions on accessibility relations and Lewis-style axioms for modal logic. Kanger failed, however, to give a completeness proof for his system;
  • Jaakko Hintikka gave a semantics in his papers introducing epistemic logic that is a simple variation of Kripke's semantics, equivalent to the characterisation of valuations by means of maximal consistent sets. He doesn't give inference rules for epistemic logic, and so cannot give a completeness proof;
  • Richard Montague had many of the key ideas contained in Kripke's work, but he did not regard them as significant, and so did not publish until after Kripke's papers had created a sensation in the logic community;
  • Evert Beth presented a semantics of intuitionistic logic based on trees, which closely resembles Kripke semantics, except for using a more cumbersome definition of satisfaction.

Though the essential ideas of Kripke semantics were very much in the air by the time Kripke first published, Saul Kripke's work on modal logic is rightly regarded as ground-breaking. Most importantly, it was Kripke who proved the completeness theorems for modal logic, and Kripke who identified the weakest normal modal logic.

Despite the seminal contribution of Kripke's work, many modal logicians deprecate the term Kripke semantics as disrespectful of the important contributions these other pioneers made. The other most widely used term possible world semantics is deprecated as inappropriate when applied to modalities other than possibility and necessity, such as in epistemic or deontic logic. Instead they prefer the terms relational semantics or frame semantics.

References

  • Modal Logic. P. Blackburn, M. de Rijke, Y. Venema. Cambridge University Press, 2001.
  • Basic Modal Logic. R. A. Bull and K. Segerberg. In The Handbook of Philosophical Logic, volume 2, pages 1--88. Kluwer, 1984.
  • A New Introduction to Modal Logic. G. E. Hughes, M. J. Cresswell. Routledge, 1996.
  • Modal Logic. A. Chagrov, M. Zakharyaschev. Oxford University Press, 1997.
  • Modal Logic. J. Garson. In E. N. Zalta, editor, The Stanford Encyclopaedia of Philosophy
  • Mathematical Modal Logic: a View of its Evolution. Robert Goldblatt. In Journal of Applied Logic, vol. 1(5-6):309-392, 2003.
  • Intuitionistic Logic. D. van Dalen. In The Handbook of Philosophical Logic, volume 3, pages 225--339. Reidel, 1986.
  • Elements of Intuitionism. M. Dummett. Clarendon Press, 1977.
  • Intuitionistic Logic, Model Theory and Forcing. M. Fitting. North-Holland, 1969.

External links



Last updated: 10-24-2004 05:10:45